委婉语研究的心智哲学视角
详细信息    本馆镜像全文|  推荐本文 |  |   获取CNKI官网全文
摘要
委婉语是一种普遍存在的语言现象,它意指用一种温和的表达方式来代替那种不够“好听”的表达方式。自产生之日起,它就担负着“润滑”交际的重任。在日常社会交际活动中,委婉语不仅已经成为人们表达思想情感的重要交际手段之一,而在语言交际中更是协调人际关系的一个重要手段。它在和谐社会构建中起着十分重要的作用
     早期学者对委婉语大多从定义、分类及美学效果等方面进行描写性或规定性的研究。当代语言学派林立,众多学者,尤其是语义学家、语用学家、认知语言学家等,借用相应的理论对委婉语提出了不同的解释方案,具有很强的解释力和创新性,也为以后委婉语的研究留下宝贵的财富。但是他们很少触及委婉语的生成和理解,所搜集的语料也是关于一些很老套的话题,例如被多次讨论的关于死亡,疾病,性,身体部位等,不具有鲜明的时代特色。本文在总结国内众多学者对委婉语研究的诸多观点基础之上,试图以新时期出现的委婉语为起点,在语言研究的心智哲学理论框架内阐释委婉语为什么可能。
     心智哲学是21世纪的第一哲学,是研究身心关系的哲学。与语言哲学不同,心智哲学不再将语言活动看作哲学直接面对的研究对象,而是把语言活动看作心智活动的反映,心智活动才是心智哲学研究的对象;语言是观察心智的“窗口”,通过这一窗口可以帮助我们观察人类心智如何运作。心智哲学与语言研究在“语言”上有交汇点,因此我们可以汲取心智哲学中可以用于语言研究的积极成果,使语言研究呈现出一种新的面貌。
     徐盛桓在心智哲学和语言研究的探索中提出语言运用的三个假设:
     (1)语言最基本的性质是:语言是基于心智的。
     (2)感觉知觉信息的表达是语言运用的基础。
     (3)语言表征的是心理表征。
     本文正是基于这三个假设,从心智哲学的视角出发,在“委婉语研究的心智哲学分析框架”下对委婉语生成和理解过程中涉及到的心智活动进行描述,进而从心智层面,主要借助意向性、心-物随附性、感受质三个概念,揭示委婉语得以应用的原因。本研究大致从两部分展开:生成过程和理解过程。生成过程又分为关指过程和选择过程。
     整个过程如下:
     第一、意向性对语言运用有极其重要的导向作用,毫无疑问对委婉语也是如此。它是说话者头脑里一系列心智活动的起点,决定了说话人的意向态度(例如,在运用委婉语时是避讳)和意向内容(需要避讳的物理事件)。否则,我们将无法进行涉世的活动,更不用说委婉地交际了。
     第二、众所周知,对于同一个“真实词语”,一般来说可能存在一个以上的委婉语来替代它,但是说话者通常只选择一个替代词来达到委婉的目的。那么,这个选择过程是如何实现的?具体来说,哪种变量在说话者选择替代词的过程中起着关键性的作用?这一答案与心-物随附性有很大的关系。心-物随附性是人们头脑里的一项重要的心智过程。一言以概之:“真实词语”的心理属性决定了说话者选择某一个委婉语来实现交际目的;该心理属性随附于物理属性但又受说话者自由意志的影响,从而在说话者头脑里涌现出一种具有委婉新质的表达,即委婉语。
     第三、听者是怎样理解这些“委婉词”的?从这样的词语里能获得什么样的感受意?这些问题的回答需要借助于感受质。感受质是心理状态的一种情形,其产生是基于心-物随附性这一心理过程。整个理解过程如下:委婉词的心理属性使得听话者产生某种感受意,引发某种积极肯定和向上的感觉。
     总之,意向性、随附性、感受质是本篇论文的理论基础。借助这些理论,我们能够在心智哲学的框架下对委婉语的产生和理解机制给出清晰的阐释。
Euphemism, as a ubiquitous language phenomenon, is a softened, bland, or sometimes neutral expression used instead of one that might suggest something unpleasant. Ever since its appearance, it has been playing a very important role in "lubricating" communication. On social occasions, euphemism has become not only one of the important communicating ways for people to express their ideas and feelings, but also a very important means to harmonize the relationships between people in verbal communications, and therefore it plays a very important role in promoting the construction of a harmonious society.
     Early researches of euphemism, descriptive or prescriptive, have been restricted to the perspectives of its definition, classification and aesthetic effects. During recent decades, modern linguistic schools stand in great numbers, which lay a solid foundation for the explanatory turn of euphemism study. Modern linguistics, cognitive semantics and cognitive pragmatics in particular, probe into this old issue by proposing different linguistic approaches with which the interpretation process has been expounded. The studies are a large treasure for further studies; however, few of scholars in the studies set foot in disclosing the generation and interpretation mechanisms of euphemism. Even if there do exist, these cursory studies merely take as the object the only limited scope of euphemistic expressions such as euphemisms about sex, illness, death, which have been the object of over-repeated examination, thus making the study somewhat devoid of the characteristics of the present time. This being the case, the present study attempts to give a tentative account of why euphemism is possible from a new perspective, the perspective of philosophy of mind.
     Philosophy of mind, being recognized as the first philosophy in the21st century by the British philosopher and linguist John Searle, is the philosophical thinking concerning the relation of body and mind. Different from philosophy of language, philosophy of mind takes mental activities as its direct object of the study with language activities only viewed as the reflection of mental activities in the scope of its study. As we all know, language is the window into mind, through which we can observe how human's mind works at large. This in turn makes it possible that philosophy of mind and the study of language have an overlapping, and thus the positive gains of the current study of euphemism from the point of view of philosophy of mind can be applied to linguistic research to make it take on a new look.
     The present study emerges from the three hypotheses of language against the background of philosophy of mind, which are put forward by the Chinese scholar Xu Shenghuan. The hypotheses are as follows:
     (1) The basic nature of language is its being mind-based.
     (2) Language use is based on what is perceived and felt.
     (3) Language representation is the reflection of mental representation.
     To be more specific, the thesis tries to describe the mental processes of the generation and interpretation of euphemism in an Analytical Framework of Euphemism Based on the Philosophy of Mind, and furthermore it reveals how the concepts of intentionality, supervenience, and qualia help to explain the mental causes for which euphemism is produced and interpreted.
     The research, which finally comes down into a mechanism about euphemism, is largely divided into two parts:generation process and interpretation process, with the former again being divided into two, the directing (that is, focusing on) process and the selecting process.
     The whole mechanism is as such:
     First, adopting the appropriate intentionality is of prior importance for language use, which undoubtedly holds true for the use of euphemism. It is the initial step of the producer, determining the producer's choice of the potential content and attitude when he speaks; that is, to be evading as to what and how he would like to express, this time to speak in a euphemistical way. Otherwise, it is impossible for us to be involved in the world, let alone speak euphemistically.
     Second, as we all know, there usually exists more than one euphemism for the same "true word", so the speaker has to choose the only one suitable to serve his or her purpose. How does the selecting process happen? To be specific, which variant is playing a decisive role in the speaker's choice of a certain substitute? This is closely related to the psychological supervenience, an important mental process which is going on in our mind. And this process can be briefed into one sentence:it is the mental property, which is somewhat dependent on the physical property of the real object described on the one hand and somewhat out of the speaker's free will of how to describe it appropriately on the other.that decides his or her choice of a certain substitute which is of euphemistic novelty.
     Third, how does the hearer interpret the "gilded words"? What qualia-sense does the hearer sense from the euphemistic word or phrases? To answer these questions, we have to resort to qualia, an instance of mental property. Its coming into being is also due to the mental process of supervenience. This interpreting process is condensed as follows:the qualia-sense of euphemism brought upon the hearer is decided by the mental property of the "gilded word" which undoubtedly arouses a kind of positive and uplifting meaning in the hearer.
     All in all, intentionality, supervenience, and qualia underlie the mechanism proposed in this thesis. By means of the three concepts, we give a clear explanation of the generation and the interpretation of euphemism from the perspective of philosophy of mind.
引文
Allan, K. Linguistic Meaning (Volume One). New York:Ruotledge&Kegan Paul World Publishing Corp,1986.
    Allan. K. and K. Burridge. Euphemism&Dysphemism:Language used as a shield and weapon. Oxford:Oxford University Press,1991.
    Austin J. Philosophical Papers[M]. Oxford:Oxford UP,1961,1979.
    Brentano,F. Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint[M]. Routledge,1993.
    Croft, William and D. Alan Cruse. Cognitive Linguistics. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,2004.
    Davidson, Donald, Mental events [A]. Reprinted in Davidson[C],1980:207-227.
    Enright, D. J. Fair of Speech:The Uses of Euphemism. Oxford:Oxford University Press,1985.
    Heidgger, Martin. The Basic Problems of Phenomenology[M]. Indiana University Press,1982:63-64.
    Husserl E. The Ideal of Phenomenology[M]. Trans. By William P. Alston and George Nakhanikian. The Hauge:Martinu Nijhoff,1973.
    Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothing:An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology[M], Trans.. By Hazel Barnes, London, Methuen&Co Ltd.,1957.
    Lakoff, George and Mark Johnson. Metaphors we live by. Chicago:University of Chicago Press,1980.
    Langacker, R. Foundations of Cognitive Grammar. Vol.1, Theoretical Prerequisites. Stanford: Stanford University Press.1987. Reprinted by北京:北京大学出版社,2001.
    Mencken, H. L. The American Language. New York:Alfred H. Knopf,1936.
    Merriam-Webster's Collegiate Dictionary.11th edition. USA:Merriam-Webster, Incorporated,2005.
    Neaman, J. S. and C. G. Silver. Kind Words:A Thesaurus of Euphemisms. Facts On File, Inc.1983. Reprinted by Beijing:World Publishing Corp,1991.
    Rawson, Hugh. A Dictionary of the Euphemisms and Other Double Talk. New York:Crown Publishers,1981.
    Rawson, Hugh. RAWSON'S Dictionary of Euphemisms and Other Doubletalk. New York: Crown Publishers,1995.
    Searle, J. Intentionality:An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind[M]. Cambridge:CUP,1983.
    Searle, J. Minds, Brains and Programs[J]. In Behavioral and Brain Sciences3:417-424.
    The New Lexicon Webster's Dictionary Of The English Languag, Volume1. New York: Lexicon publications.inc.1988.
    Ungerer F.&H. J. Schmid. An Introduction to Cognitive Linguistics. Addison Wesley Longman Ltd.1996. Reprinted by北京:外语教学与研究出版社,2001.
    Verschueren, Jef. Understanding Pragmatics. Edward Arnold (Publishers) Ltd.1999. Reprinted by北京:外语教学与研究出版社,2000.
    Warren, B. What euphemisms tell us about interpretation of words. Studia linguistica: Vol.4612(1992):128-172.
    Webster'Third New International Dictionary. USA:Merriam-Webster,1961.
    Williams, J. M. Origins of the English Language. New York:Free Press,1957.
    Wittgenstein L. Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics[M].(Ed.).GH. von. Wright,1956:40.
    http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Intentionalit
    http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Supervenience
    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/dualism/
    http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Qualia
    蔡曙山.关于哲学、心理学和认知科学12个问题与塞尔教授的对话[J].《学术界》,2007,3:7-17.——.人类心智探秘的哲学之路——试论从语言哲学到心智哲学的发展[J].《晋阳学刊》,2010,3:3-11.
    陈嘉映.《语言哲学》[M].北京:北京大学出版社,2003.
    陈道望.《修辞学发凡》[M].上海:上海教育出版社,1997.
    陈晓平.“随附性”概念辨析[J].《哲学研究》,2010,4:71-80.
    陈原.《社会语言学》[M].上海:学林出版社,1983.
    范家材.《英语修辞赏析》[M].上海:上海交通大学出版社,1992.
    方晓梅.简述英语职业委婉语的社会功能[J].《黄山学院学报》,2008,3.
    付珊珊.委婉语研究的逻辑视角(硕士论文),2007.
    何爱晶.心智哲学观照下的名-动转类思维机制研究[J].《外国语文》,2010,5.——.歇后语研究新论-心智哲学的观点[J].《现代外语》,2011,4.
    贺学贵.广告英语中委婉语的应用[J].《商场现代化》2007.
    李国南.英语中的委婉语[J].《外国语》1989(3):23-27.
    李军华.汉语委婉语的社会文化构成及语用发展[J].《广西社会科学》,2005,12.
    梁红梅.“委婉语的语用分析”[J].《天津外国语学院学报》,2000,(1),30—34.
    刘纯豹.《英语委婉语词典》[M].北京:商务印书馆.
    刘景钊.《意向性-心智关指世界的能力》[M].北京:中国社会科学出版社,2001.
    罗春风,陈洁.“从社会文化心理看委婉语”[J].《郑州航空工业管理学院学报》,2003,(6),34—35.
    彭文钊.委婉语——社会文化域的语言映射[J].《外国语》,1999(1):66-71.
    束定芳.委婉语新探[J].《外国语》,1989(3):28-34.——,徐金元.委婉语研究:回顾与前瞻[J].《外国语》,1995(5):17-22.
    孙汝建.《修辞的社会心理分析》[M].上海:上海外语教育出版社,2005.
    王雅军.《实用委婉语辞典》[M].上海:上海辞书出版社,2005.
    吴礼权.论委婉修辞生成的心理机制[J].《修辞学习》,1998(2):43-44.
    徐海铭.委婉语的语用研究[J].《外语研究》,1996(3):21-24.
    徐盛桓.语言研究的心智哲学视角——“心智哲学与语言研究”之五[J].《河南大学学报》(社科版),2011,4.——.“移就”为什么可能?[J].《外语教学与研究》,2011,5.——.心智哲学与语言研究[J].《外国语文》,2010,5.——.心智哲学与认知语言学创新[J].《北京科技大学学报》(社会科学版),2010,1.——.心理模型与类层级结构,认知语言学讲习班提纲(长沙,2007b.5)——.转喻为什么可能[J].《上海交通大学学报》(社会科学版)2008a(1):69-77.——.修辞研究的新进路[J].《西安外国语大学学报》,2008d.
    徐盛桓,陈香兰.感受质与感受意[J].《现代外语》,2010,4:331-339.
    于亚伦.当代英语委婉语初探[J].《外语学刊》,1984(2):45-49.
    张拱贵.《汉语委婉语词典》[M].北京:北京语言文化大学出版社,1996.

© 2004-2018 中国地质图书馆版权所有 京ICP备05064691号 京公网安备11010802017129号

地址:北京市海淀区学院路29号 邮编:100083

电话:办公室:(+86 10)66554848;文献借阅、咨询服务、科技查新:66554700